Awesome
JonPRL is a proof refinement logic in the sense of λ-PRL or Nuprl; JonPRL inherits its computational type theory from Constable, Bates, Harper, Allen, Bickford, Howe, Smith and many other names. Computational Type Theory is based on a meaning explanation similar to the ones which Martin-Löf introduced in 1979, to which I have written a self-contained introduction, Type Theory and its Meaning Explanations.
Discussion and Questions
There is an IRC channel on freenode at #jonprl.
Building & Installing JonPRL
JonPRL uses SML/NJ's CM for its build. First make sure you have SML/NJ set up properly. Then, install JonPRL's dependencies:
git submodule update --init --recursive
Then, JonPRL may be built using its Makefile
:
make smlnj
make test
This puts a binary in ./bin/jonprl
. Optionally, you may install JonPRL globally using:
sudo make install
Running JonPRL
To run JonPRL, simply direct it at your development:
jonprl example/test.jonprl
You may specify as many files as you like in this command; they will be refined in order, in case of any dependencies.
Emacs Mode
Optionally, you may install the JonPRL Mode for Emacs.
Basic Syntax
JonPRL has a two-level syntax. There is the syntax of terms in the underlying
lambda calculus (the object language) and the syntax of tactics and definitions
in the metalanguage. Terms from the underlying lambda calculus are embedded
into the metalanguage using brackets ([
and ]
). When referring to names
from the object language in the metalanguage, they are quoted in angle brackets
(<
and >
).
The syntax of the object language represents all binders in a
consistent manner. The variables to be bound in a subterm are written
before it with a dot. For example, the identity function is written
λ(x.x)
where the first x
indicates the bound name and the second
refers back to it, and the first projection of a pair P
is written
spread(P; x.y.x)
. The semicolon separates arguments to spread
.
Top-level declarations
JonPRL provides four top-level declarations:
Operator
gives the binding structure of a new operator.=def=
defines the meaning of an operator in terms of the existing operators.Theorem
declares a theorem, and allows it to be proven.Tactic
defines a tactic in terms of the built-in tactics.
Built-in operators
Together with the syntax for binding trees, the built-in operators of JonPRL constitute the core type theory, in combination with the rules for CTT which are built into JonPRL's refiner. In this section, several of the operators is presented together with its arity and a brief informal description. An arity is a list of the valences of an operator's subterms; valence is the number of variables to bind.
abstract form | concrete form | description |
---|---|---|
unit() | unit | The unit type |
<>() | <> | The trivial inhabitant of unit |
fun(0;1) | (x:A) B , A -> B | The dependent function type |
lam(1) | lam(x.E) | The lambda abstraction |
ap(0;0) | M N | Function application |
isect(0;1) | {x:A} B , A => B | The family intersection type |
prod(0;1) | (x:A) * B , A * B | The dependent pair type |
pair(0;0) | <M,N> | The pair operator |
spread(0;2) | spread(M; x.y.E) | Pattern matching for pairs |
subset(0;1) | `{x:A | B}` |
plus(0;0) | A + B | The disjoint union type |
inl(0) | inl(M) | The left union introduction form |
inr(0) | inr(M) | The right union introduction form |
decide(0;1;1) | decide(M; l.E; r.F) | Pattern matching for disjoint unions |
void() | void | The empty type |
=(0;0;0) | =(M;N;A) | The equality type (M,N are equal at type A ) |
member(0;0) | member(M;A) | The membership type (M is a member of A ) |
so_apply(0;0) | F[x] | Application for second order variables |
Second-order variables
Unlike some other implementations of type theory that use the same syntax for
function application and filling in second-order variables, JonPRL's
second-order variables must be applied using the so_apply(0;0)
operator
(written using brackets, F[x]
).
As an example, unique existence might be defined as follows:
Operator ex_uni : (0;1).
[ex_uni(T;x.P[x])] =def= [(x:T) * P[x] * {y:T} P[y] => =(x;y;T)].
Note that P
is applied to x
and y
using so_apply
rather than
ap
, which is reserved for function application.
Computational Equivalence
The elements of base()
are all closed terms. Their equality is ceq(0;0)
,
which denotes Howe's computational
equivalence. Two terms are
computationally equivalent if they both diverge or if they run to equivalent
results. Computational equivalence is a congruence, which means that one can
also prove that two terms are computationally equivalent if their subterms are
computationally equivalent.